Book
Review: 'Political Order and Political Decay' by Francis Fukuyama
Human beings possess biologically rooted
imperatives to favor kith and kin. Political order requires checking these
impulses.
By David Polansky in
the Wall Street Journal
If
the title were not already taken, "A Brief History of Time" might
serve to describe Francis Fukuyama's latest opus, "Political Order and
Political Decay," together with its prequel, "The Origins of
Political Order" (2011). Between these two volumes, he ranges across a
good span of recorded history (and before), mining lessons about "the
underlying rules by which societies organize themselves" as he seeks to
update his mentor Samuel Huntington's classic 1968 work of political sociology,
"Political Order in Changing Societies."
While
Mr. Fukuyama's earlier book discussed all of human history up to Napoleon's
1806 victory at Jena, this volume more modestly confines itself to the
subsequent period through the present day. This temporal division marks the
beginning of the period in which a particular set of political institutions—the
modern state, the rule of law and accountable government—developed, with
increasing speed, into the dominant model of sociopolitical organization around
the world. Mr. Fukuyama pithily sums up this world-historical process as
"getting to Denmark."
"Political
Order and Political Decay" is divided into four thematic sections: the
establishment of the modern state in Western Europe and North America; its
expansion, with varying degrees of success, to other regions of the world; the
concurrent spread (and waxing and waning) of democracy; and the degeneration of
formerly successful democratic state institutions, particularly in the United
States (the "political decay" of the title).
Mr.
Fukuyama—to his credit—largely avoids pitching a Big Idea That Explains It All.
But to the extent that he has an overarching narrative, it is this: Human
beings are possessed of certain biologically rooted imperatives to favor kith
and kin over others—what he calls patrimonialism. Successful political order
entails the establishment of institutions that check and redirect these
impulses in productive and publicly beneficial ways. Since the Industrial
Revolution and the spread of market capitalism (i.e., globalization), the
institutions that most successfully accomplish this feat have been the modern
state coupled with the rule of law and some degree of democratic
accountability. What we call corruption is really the imperfect realization (or
absence) of such institutions. Political decay, to which the final section of
this work is devoted, is the condition where public institutions, grown
sclerotic over time, prove increasingly unable to manage the natural
reassertion of patrimonial impulses.
Rather
than attribute these outcomes to any single cause, Mr. Fukuyama prefers to
trace in each case the various interacting processes that have produced order
and decay. Consequently, much (perhaps too much) of this work is largely given
over to synthesizing and reproducing the secondary literature on a dizzying
array of topics. The reader cannot but be impressed by the facility with which
he introduces and swiftly outlines such matters as the social construction of
nationhood, the legitimacy gap afflicting governments in modern-day
Mediterranean countries, Montesquieu's account of the relationship between
geography and institutions, et very much cetera.
In
his last section Mr. Fukuyama aims to make good on the promise implicit in the
title of the first chapter of his first volume: "The Necessity of
Politics." According to him, the political order that grants us valuable
goods like security and wealth requires continuous management to survive.
Political order is meanwhile necessary because of our natural, prepolitical state:
An innate tendency to revert to conditions of rival kinship groups is both a
cause and effect of political decay. As he puts it, "the problem of
patrimonialism is never finally solved in any political system."
Thus
Mr. Fukuyama presents political order as a (continuing) artificial solution to
a natural problem. It comes as some surprise, then, when he concludes with an
endorsement of Aristotle's famous definition of human beings as political
animals. Aristotle in fact shares with Mr. Fukuyama the view that our strongest
inclinations are biological and, like Mr. Fukuyama, contends that practical
politics must take these into account. But Aristotle also claims that "the
purpose of politics is not to make living together possible, but to make living
well possible." For Aristotle, our ability to reason about what living
well entails is the outstanding feature of the human animal, and it is what
makes politics necessary—whereas Mr. Fukuyama suggests that politics has the
more limited role of simply enabling innately disputatious humans to live
together at all.
Though
Mr. Fukuyama has been both a policy maker and adviser, he eschews explicit
policy recommendations here. Instead, he has sought to clarify the fundamental
problems of political order. His account rests upon a remarkably broad
synthetic definition of human nature, drawing on sociobiology, sociology and
political philosophy. The trouble is that these streams do not necessarily
converge. They differ regarding the relationship of human nature to political
life, and this has important implications for which aspect of political order
deserves our most urgent attention. If our natural impulses are prepolitical,
then stronger state institutions are required to keep us in check and perhaps
our degree of political participation ought to be limited. If, on the other
hand, we are indeed political by nature, then the problem may lie more in the
quality of our civic participation than in its degree.
Thus,
in a work on political order, the reader may be left wondering: Is politics the
problem or the solution?
Mr. Polansky is a doctoral student in political
science at the University of Toronto.
No comments:
Post a Comment